About | HeinOnline Law Journal Library | HeinOnline Law Journal Library | HeinOnline

69 J. Crim. L. & Criminology 291 (1978)
Death Penalty, Retribution and Penal Policy, The

handle is hein.journals/jclc69 and id is 297 raw text is: 9901-4169/78/6903-0291S02.00/0
Tiui JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAWv & CRIMINOL.OGY                                                Vol. 69, No. 3
Copyright © 1978 by Northwestern University School of Law                                  Pin t d in U.S.A.
THE DEATH PENALTY, RETRIBUTION AND PENAL POLICY
JACK P. GIBBS*

No special training in psychology is required to
infer that Supreme Court Justices have agonized a
great deal over the death penalty in recent years.
They are badly split on the issue, and it would be
difficult to exaggerate the importance of the ra-
tionale that some of the Justices have offered for
not rejecting capital punishment as unconstitu-
tional.1 The rationale is not a belief in the deterrent
efficacy of capital punishment. To the contrary,
there is appreciable consensus among the Justices
that evidence of deterrence is far too inconclusive
to justify the death penalty. Yet, some of the
Justices are willing to entertain a distinctly differ-
ent argument-that retribution is a sufficient jus-
tification for legal executions-and the retributive
doctrine is currently receiving support from nu-
merous prominent scholars.2
RESURRECTION WITHOUT A CORPSE
Although the seeming resurrection of the retri-
butive doctrine at the highest judicial level may
appear to be the ultimate manifestation of the
national clamor for law and order, that interpre-
tation is a gross oversimplification. For one thing,
a resurrection requires a corpse, and the retributive
doctrine was never truly buried in the cemetery of
ideas. To be sure, a host of critics have condemned
retribution as barbaric, thereby creating the
impression that the doctrine is an anachronism.3
That is all the more the case because prominent
critics of the retributive doctrine have been truly
educated individuals. Hence, the tacit suggestion
is that the doctrine was invented and is now per-
petuated by rednecks. Yet two great names in
the history of philosophy, Hegel and Kant, were
uncompromising retributivists.4 For that matter,
* Professor of Sociology, Vanderbilt University.
'See, e.g., Gregg v. Georgia, 428 U.S. 153 (1976) (plu-
rality and concurring opinions); Furman v. Georgia, 408
U.S. 238 (1972).
2 See, e.g., G. NEWMAN, THE PUNISHMENT RESPONSE
(1978); E. VAN DEN HAAG, PUNISHING CRIMINALS: CON-
CERNING A VERY OLD AND PAINFUL QUESTION (1975);
A. VON HIRSCH, DOING JUSTICE (1976).
3 Seegenerally K. MENNINGER, THE CRIME OF PUNISH-
MENT 190 (1968).
4See G. HEGEL, PHILOSOPHY OF RIGHT (T. Knox
trans. 1952) and I. KAmr, THE PHILOSOPHY OF LAW (W.
Hastie trans. 1887).

philosophers did not succumb to the anti-punitive
orientation that swept the social and behavioral.
sciences between 1938 and 1968,5 and thus one
finds the staunchest defenders of the retributive
doctrine  among   contemporary  philosophers.6
Needless to say, whatever their moral or intellectual
defects may be, those philosophers are hardly red-
necks.
Returning to the main argument, if Supreme
Court Justices have come to a reconsideration of
retribution, the impetus was not their sensitivity to
public opinion but, rather, their doubts about
deterrence and recognition that the idea of reha-
bilitating criminals has fallen into disrepute. To be
sure, even now there is no truly conclusive evidence
that rehabilitation programs in criminal correc-
tions have failed to check recidivism, but those who
demand conclusive evidence before reshaping
penal policy may well wait forever. In any case,
those who have marshalled the evidence-such as
Kassebaum and Lipton-are not all retributivists7
Perhaps the rehabilitation  programs were
doomed to fail because of limited financial support
and the custodial context in which many of those
programs were implemented. Be that as it may, the
Supreme Court cannot direct revenues into reha-
bilitation programs or eliminate prisons with a
view to furthering rehabilitative programs.
ALTERNATIVES TO RETRIBUTION
As previously suggested, the retributive doctrine
is now being revitalized not only because its chief
contender-rehabilitation-no longer commands
a strong following, but also because of the uncon-
vincing evidence generated by deterrence research.
5 Andenaes, General Prevention Revisited: Research and Pol-
icy Implications, 66J. CRIM. L. & C. 338 (1975); Johnston,
Punishment of Hwnan Behavior, 27 AM. PSYCH. 1033 (1972);
Singer, Psychological Studies of Punishment, 58 CALIF. L.
REV. 405 (1970).
6 See H. Fingarette, Punishment and Suffering, Presi-
dential Address, Fifty-first Annual Pacific Meeting of the
American Philosophical Association (March, 1977).
7G. KASSEBAUM, D. WARD, & D. WILNER, PRISON
TREATMENr AND PAROLE SURVIVAL: AN EMPIRICAL
ASSESSMENI (1971); D. LIPTON, R. MARTrINSON, & J.
WILKS, THE EFFEarIVENESS OF CORRECTIONAL
TREArMEN : A SURVEY OF TREATMENT EVALUATION
SrUDIES (1975).

What Is HeinOnline?

HeinOnline is a subscription-based resource containing thousands of academic and legal journals from inception; complete coverage of government documents such as U.S. Statutes at Large, U.S. Code, Federal Register, Code of Federal Regulations, U.S. Reports, and much more. Documents are image-based, fully searchable PDFs with the authority of print combined with the accessibility of a user-friendly and powerful database. For more information, request a quote or trial for your organization below.



Short-term subscription options include 24 hours, 48 hours, or 1 week to HeinOnline.

Contact us for annual subscription options:

Already a HeinOnline Subscriber?

profiles profiles most