About | HeinOnline Law Journal Library | HeinOnline Law Journal Library | HeinOnline

25 Fed. L. Rev. 1 (1997)
Originalism in Constitutional Interpretation

handle is hein.journals/fedlr25 and id is 5 raw text is: ORIGINALISM IN CONSTITUTIONAL INTERPRETATION
Jeffrey Goldsworthy*
Our duty is to declare the law as enacted in the Constitution and not to add to its
provisions new doctrines which may happen to conform to our own prepossessions.1
1 INTRODUCTION
In this article I will discuss two questions concerning originalism in Australian
constitutional law. The questions are, first, the extent to which the contemporary
meanings of constitutional provisions, express or implied, are the same as their original
meanings in 1900, when the Constitution was created; and secondly, the extent to
which those original meanings are determined by the intentions of the people
responsible for creating it (whom I will call the founders2). These two questions are
distinct. Almost all literary critics would agree that the language in Shakespeare's plays
should be understood in its original sixteenth century sense, but many would deny that
any other evidence of Shakespeare's intentions is relevant in interpreting it. Similarly, a
literalist, who believes that the meaning of the Constitution is exhausted by the
meanings of its words, could hold that their original literal meanings are critical, but
reject the relevance of any other evidence of the founders' intentions.
I will argue that both original meanings and original intentions help determine the
contemporary meaning of the Constitution. But the position I will defend can aptly be
described as moderate originalism, because it falls somewhere between more extreme
versions of originalism and non-originalism. My defence of that position will be both
descriptive and normative: I will argue that moderate originalism is more faithful than
its rivals to legal precedents and conventions, and more attractive from the perspective
of political morality.
Recent decisions of the High Court suggest uncertainty and even ambivalence in
approaching these questions. For example, in a number of cases over the last ten years,
it has relied heavily on evidence of the founders' intentions, evidence which it would
not previously have been willing even to consult; yet more recently, in dealing with
Associate Professor of Law, Monash University. This article originated as a paper
presented at the Workshop on Legal Interpretation, organised by the Social and Political
Theory Group, Research School of Social Sciences, Australian National University, on
September 12, 1996. I am grateful to participants at the Workshop for their comments, and
to Richard Holton and Rae Langton for commenting on an earlier presentation.
AG (Cth); ex rel McKinlay v Commonwealth (1975) 135 CLR 1 at 44 per Gibbs J.
2   Just who these people should be taken to have been - those who drafted and debated the
Constitution in Constitutional Conventions, the voters who approved it in referendums,
the members of the Imperial Parliament who enacted it - is discussed in Part 5, below.

What Is HeinOnline?

HeinOnline is a subscription-based resource containing thousands of academic and legal journals from inception; complete coverage of government documents such as U.S. Statutes at Large, U.S. Code, Federal Register, Code of Federal Regulations, U.S. Reports, and much more. Documents are image-based, fully searchable PDFs with the authority of print combined with the accessibility of a user-friendly and powerful database. For more information, request a quote or trial for your organization below.



Short-term subscription options include 24 hours, 48 hours, or 1 week to HeinOnline.

Contact us for annual subscription options:

Already a HeinOnline Subscriber?

profiles profiles most