About | HeinOnline Law Journal Library | HeinOnline Law Journal Library | HeinOnline

42 Law & Phil. 1 (2023)

handle is hein.journals/lwphil42 and id is 1 raw text is: 




Law  and Philosophy (2023) 42: 1-36    © The Author(s), under exclusive licence to Springer Nature B.V. 2022
https://doi.org/10.1007/s10982-022-09449-7





                          WILLIAM R. TADROS



             COERCION WITHOUT INCAPACITATION




                            (Accepted   6 April 2022)



ABSTRACT. This essay examines why coerced conduct tends not to have the
moral  and legal consequences  that non-coerced  conduct often has. In it, I argue
against the incapacitation approach, the view that coerced conduct tends not to
result in the coercer acquiring a permission or an entitlement because the coercee
is typically incapable of exercising her rights to change the coercer's permissions or
entitlements. After demonstrating that coercees retain the ability to exercise those
rights, this article develops an alternative account: that coerced conduct tends not
to have a licensing effect because coercees typically do not elect to effect a change
in their coercers' permissions or entitlements.


Coerced conduct tends not to have the legal or moral consequences
that  non-coerced conduct often has.1 In the United States, for in-
stance,  a defendant   who pleads guilty is deemed not to have waived
her  Sixth Amendment right to a jury trial when her plea is the result
of  constitutionally   impermissible coercive pressure.2 Similarly, it is
generally   accepted   that a blackmail   victim  typically  does  not  give up
her  moral entitlement to the money that she hands to the black-
mailer.  Clarifying  why   coerced   conduct   tends  not  to have  a licensing
effect, in other  words,   explaining  why   coerced   conduct   typically does

   ' To simplify the prose, throughout this paper I will use the male pronoun when referring to the
proposal-maker (whether the individual is a coercer, a would-be coercer, or an issuer of a non-coercive
proposal) and the female pronoun when referring to the proposal-recipient (i.e., a coercee, an intended
victim, or a recipient of a non-coercive proposal).
   2 See Brady v. United States, 397 U.S. 742, 750 (1970) ([A]gents of the State may not produce a plea by
actual or threatened physical harm or by mental coercion overbearing the will of the defendant.).
Because the coercive pressure must be constitutionally impermissible to invalidate a plea deal, not
everything that a layman might view as a threat invalidates a plea deal. See, e.g., United States v. Pollard,
959 F.2d 1011 (D.C. Cir. 1992) (holding that because the government had adequate evidence of the
defendant's guilt, and because the government was entitled to prosecute the defendant's wife, consti-
tutionally impermissible coercion did not occur even if, as the defendant claimed, he pleaded guilty
because prosecutors otherwise refused to negotiate a plea deal with his wife, who suffered from a
debilitating gastrointestinal disorder that caused her to lose 40 pounds during a three-month stay in
jail).

What Is HeinOnline?

HeinOnline is a subscription-based resource containing thousands of academic and legal journals from inception; complete coverage of government documents such as U.S. Statutes at Large, U.S. Code, Federal Register, Code of Federal Regulations, U.S. Reports, and much more. Documents are image-based, fully searchable PDFs with the authority of print combined with the accessibility of a user-friendly and powerful database. For more information, request a quote or trial for your organization below.



Short-term subscription options include 24 hours, 48 hours, or 1 week to HeinOnline.

Contact us for annual subscription options:

Already a HeinOnline Subscriber?

profiles profiles most